StatCounter Code

Tuesday, May 1, 1979

Solid Gold


May, 1979                     



MARX, THE ANTI-SEMITE
By TOM MILSTEIN



      Despite generations of socialist cover-up, obscurantism and bowdlerization, the fact that Karl Marx was an anti-Semite, that he reviled Judaism as a religion and Jews as people, is so well established by his own writings as to be beyond reasonable dispute. What remains unclear is the meaning of this anti-Semitism. A number of explanations have been offered, none very satisfactory.
     For most Marxists, the subject is an embarrassing one.  Some deny that he was anti-Semitic “in the modern sense,” arguing that his hostility to Judaism was cut from the same cloth is his hostility to Christianity and to religion in general. This view will not withstand a serious reading of what Marx actually had to say about Jews and Judaism. His statements have a very “modern’’—not to say Hitlerian—ring to them, and moreover reveal a special loathing for the Jews which transcend his critique of Christianity or for that matter religion as such. Marx’s attitude toward Christianity at its most negative, was merely sarcastic and iconoclastic, and he never lost a certain maudlin empathy, toward it—Marx’s daughter Eleanor reports that “Again and again I heard him say: ‘Despite everything, we can forgive Christianity much, for it has taught to love children’.”  Toward religion in general he could show real poetic feeling, even when attacking it, as in the lines which precede his famous “opium of the people” dictum: “Religious suffering is at the same time an expression of real suffering and a protest against real suffering.  Religion is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the sentiment of a heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions.”  There is no such compassionate sensitivity to be found in his attitude toward Judaism.
     Other Marxists acknowledge the anti-Semitism, but brush it off as merely a reigning prejudice of the age. Aside from the fact that Marx is not notable for succumbing to the reigning prejudices of his age—why should he have acquiesced in this one? -- this explanation does no  justice to the obsessiveness of Marx’s anti-Semitism. It appears in every field of his literary activity, his polemics, his journalism, his treatises on philosophy and politics, his correspondence above all and most vulgarly, his correspondence. And it appears in the form of a passion, not the grand passion of his life, to be sure, but still a nagging theme to which he would recur in the most irrelevant contexts—his rivalry with Lasalle, for example—and in the most defamatory and emotion-laden terms. We are dealing with more than a mere quirk, either of Marx or his times.
     Socialist anti-capitalism has been invoked as another explanation. There is a long tradition of socialist willingness to exploit the stereotypical identification of Jews with the commercial spirit, to make the Jews personifications of capitalist evil, which certainly antedates Marx. Marx is represented as merely inheriting and thoughtlessly continuing this demagogic tradition in the propaganda of anti-capitalism. But Marx rejected the simplistic anti-capitalism of the radical tradition. One of the touchstones by which he distinguished his theory of socialism from its “utopian” predecessors was its subtly inflected critique of capitalism, which stressed capitalism’s historically progressive mission as the solvent of tradition and custom’s bonds and the organizer of colossal productive forces—both of which functions he regarded as the sine qua non of socialism.  As is well known, Marx was quite capable of praising capitalism to the skies, especially when defending it against the primitive and—to his way of thinking—reactionary attacks of “unscientific” socialism.
     Marx’s anti-capitalism is therefore no explanation of his anti-Semitism, even if he did partake in socialism’s traditional identification of Judaism with the spirit of capitalism. Such an identification would, logically, have led Marx to all evaluation of Judaism at least as nuanced and dialectical as his critique of capitalism itself. Instead, we find a striking disparity between Marx’s unmodulated hatred toward the Jews and thing for which he is alleged to have hated them, their capitalistic spirit. It is the same disparity which we earlier noted between his attitudes toward Christianity and Judaism.
     The incongruity of Marx’s anti-Semitism, its glaring inconsistency with the general tenor of his thought, not to mention its morbid odor, has led many students of Marx to the selbsthass thesis. Marx’s anti-Semitism is to be understood primarily in terms of the psychology of the self-hating Jew.  The biographical facts of Marx’s life, particularly those connected with the less than wholehearted conversion of his father to Christianity, tend to support this thesis. Additional circumstantial evidence is provided by familiarity with the stresses of marginality to which European Jews were exposed in the 19th century, stresses which were only partially relieved—in certain ways, actually sharpened—by exercising the conversion option.
     The self-hatred thesis has been strenuously resisted by many socialists, despite overwhelming evidence that more was involved in Marx’s anti-Semitism than casual or typical prejudice, doubtless because of the difficulty of reconciling the image of Marx as a titan in the modern struggle for human liberation, with the rather sordid evidence of a neurotically twisted character. The only alternative, however, would be to swallow the Great Man’s bigotry; and that alternative is simply not available to a civilized person in the 20th century, socialist, Marxist, or whatever. So, unpleasant though it may be, the self-hatred thesis stands as the most reasonable explanation of Marx’s anti-Semitism. It locates the source of a major warp in his thinking, obsessively clung to, in an appropriately irrational source—inner shame at being something other, something less, than a real German.
     As an explanation, self-hatred seems right. The trouble is that it has been made to serve as more than an explanation. It has become a way of encysting the problem, as though Marx’s anti-Semitism were a characterological carbuncle, diseased in itself, but fortunately walled off from the healthy surrounding tissues of his thought. No attention whatever has been paid to the possible relationship, whether causal or symptomatic, between his anti-Semitism and his other ideas. Certainly acceptance of the self-hatred explanation does not warrant this reticence, for self-hatred deals with the motivation of Marx’s anti-Semitism, and does not even address the matter of its implications for the rest of his thought.
     One can already hear the cries of the Marxists: “Marx’s anti-Semitism had no such implications! It may have been a serious character flaw, but that is all it was.” But if it was a serious flaw (i.e., serious enough to be rooted in something as perverse as self-hatred), how could it fail to be reflected in the rest of his thought? More to the point, is this effort to pigeonhole an inconvenient and distasteful biographical and intellectual fact at all consistent with the method Marx would have pursued? To treat Marx’s anti-Semitism as an embarrassment is to destroy its significance as a clue, an outcropping of hitherto unsuspected strata of meanings. It was his method to follow such cryptic manifestations wherever they led, no matter whose lovely intellectual castles were undermined in the pursuit. Perhaps for Marxists this method loses its charm when their own ideological ramparts risk being breached—and perhaps this would be another occasion on which Marx would have to deny being a “Marxist.”


     Anti-Semitism stands for Marx’s blindness to the roots of Western civilization, which he exalted, in “Oriental despotism,” which he abominated. This blindness, which pervades his theory of history and therefore his strategy for socialism, represents the submerged eight-ninths of an iceberg of which anti-Semitism was merely the visible protrusion. It is the blindness which led him to view the West as a self-developing entity, governed solely by its own internal laws of class struggle, and to disregard the plain evidence of decisive Eastern influence at critical junctures in the West’s development. One of these influences, an influence without which the unique development of the West would have been impossible, is expressed in the role of monotheism in Western history, and it is the Jews, symbols and bearers of monotheism, whom Marx traduces.
     For Marx, there could be no such influence. The relationship between East and West was strictly one of contrasts and polar opposites. Oriental despotism he portrayed as a “generalized system of state slavery,” presided over by a supreme autocrat and his bureaucracy which concentrated both economic and political power in one gargantuan administration, and which preyed upon a mass of dispersed agrarian villages, each one related to the next only by the unifying force of centralized state coercion and exploitation. This system he denoted the “Asiatic mode of production,” and emphasized that it did not undergo historical development (i.e., institutional change through time) but only expanded until it reached its natural geographical limits (i.e., development across space), after which it assumed the aspect of a static, unchanging cosmos “always [showing] an unchanging social infrastructure coupled with unceasing change in the persons and tribes who manage to ascribe to themselves the political superstructure.”  In other words, Oriental society lacked all capacity for self-development.
     The West, on the other hand, was the self-developing civilization around which Marx built his whole theory of history. According to this theory, history was a series of stages in the development of the means of production, each one constituting a mode of production with its own characteristic division of labor, out of which grew its particular class relationships, political struggles, and cultural products. While Marx was a good deal more flexible in his portrayal of the relationship between the economic base and its corresponding superstructure than most of his “Marxist” followers, the fact is that he presented the history of the West as a unilinear process of development driven by forces originating in the economic base. Each mode of production expanded to its maximum potential, after which its inherent but formerly muted contradictions burst to the surface. The social and political upheavals expressing these contradictions culminated in a social revolution which overthrew the old mode of production (and all the social relations based on it) and replaced it with a new and more advanced mode. From this conception stemmed Marx’s famous schema of the historical process: primitive communism, classical slavery, feudalism, capitalism and finally, socialism.
     Now Marx specifically warned against “[metamorphosing] my historical sketch of the genesis of capitalism in Western Europe into an historico-philosophical theory of the general path every people is fated to tread...” in a letter discussing the misapplication of his ideas to developments in Russia. From this and other evidence (e.g. his use of a geographic term to distinguish the Asiatic mode of production as opposed to the historical and analytical terms he used to describe the other modes) it is clear that he did not intend his unilinear theory of Western history—ancient, feudal, bourgeois—to be generalized into a unilinear theory of world history. But his becomingly modest posture Marx belied on the numerous occasions when he insisted that history itself was a characteristic of the West, because Oriental despotism lacked the inner dynamic of forces necessary to evolve: “Indian society has no history at all, at least no known history. What we call its history, is but the. history of successive invaders who founded their empires on the passive basis of that unresisting and unchanging society.”
     In other words, Marx’s theory of history applies only to the West, and not to the world as a whole. But the Oriental despotic world outside of the West, the world of the Asiatic mode of production, has no history. Therefore, insofar as there is such a thing as human history, Marx’s theory is its universal key, his modest disclaimers to the contrary notwithstanding. Marx’s qualifications do not yield the image of a world made up of two separate streams, but rather of one stream and one stagnant pond.
     Since he identified history exclusively with the West, Marx felt obliged to explain that history solely in terms of forces originating in the West. That is the meaning of his theory of history: the self-development of the West, as against the stagnation and fossilization of Oriental despotism. The theory’s actual content—“The history of all hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles”—represents Marx’s effort to identify the mechanism by which this self-development took place, the common thread linking together and mediating between the different forms of social organization which, each in its turn, make up the history of the West. According to the theory, the classical slavery of Greek and Roman antiquity grows out of primitive communism, feudalism out of classical slavery, and capitalism out of feudalism. Each system develops embryonically from within the system it is destined to replace; it replaces it because of a superior organization of the productive forces. Class struggle is the replacement process and therefore the motor of history.
     History—the development of one social system out of another—is composed of the interaction of classes. What then is made when whole social systems interact? The significance of this question emerges when it is recalled that the concept of class struggle is central to Marx’s unilinear theory of history. In order for him to present the history of the West at all, in contradistinction to the stagnation of the East, he had to portray is as a self-developing entity. Classes struggled; one social system changed into another. Only classes interacted, therefore: social systems, societies modes of production were the product of that interaction and did not themselves interact, being temporally separated (“stages”) in the historical process. Marx’s theory of history therefore cannot allow the possibility of significant interaction between different social systems.*

-------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
•           Obviously, Marx dealt with the phenomenon of revolutionary war between nations possessing different social systems—indeed, it was the only kind of relation he could imagine between them—but he treated such events as a special case of class struggle in its revolutionary climax. Since such conflicts always took place between nations embodying the ancien regime and a nation or nations embodying its revolutionary replacement, the narrative sequence of his unilinear theory was not upset by them. Also, while Marx’s theory could not acknowledge interaction between differing social systems, Marx himself could, as his observations concerning Russia’s relationship to Europe show. But he never integrated these observations into his theory of history. Indeed, they cannot be so integrated.
-------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

            But all of the social systems which Marx defines as “stages” in the historical progress of the West interacted with, and were profoundly influenced by, Oriental despotism, the system which he excluded from history. When Hellenic Greece became the Hellenistic Empire, it was manifesting such influence, as was Republican Rome when it became Imperial Rome. In both cases the result of extensive conquests of Oriental despotic societies was a partial “orientalization” of the conqueror. Feudalism did not grow “organically” out of the contradictions of classical slavery; it was rather a synthesis of the Oriental despotism of the late Roman Empire and the tribalism of the invading barbarians who overthrew it. Capitalism may have sheltered in the “interstices” of feudalism, but that is not the same thing at all as developing out of its “contradictions”; in point of fact the commercial technique indispensable to Western capitalist development was unlikely to have arisen spontaneously out of feudal agriculture and was in any case imported from the East, where it did arise, thousands of years before European feudalism even existed. Socialism too was supposed to develop out of the contradictions of capitalism; instead it has become Oriental despotism’s ideology of liberation from Western imperialism and of modernization.
     From the standpoint of Marx’s theory of history, of history conceived as the record of the West’s self-development, these Eastern influences on the West’s history are inadmissible. Had Marx acknowledged them, he would have had to explain them. To have explained them, he would have had to abandon his whole unilinear scheme, according to which the West advances, from antiquity to modern times, through a fixed sequence of stages, by means of its own inherent dynamism. In place of the unilinear scheme, he would have had to advance a model of Western development which viewed it as the outcome of a process of hybridization, of internal class struggle plus the persisting external influence of Oriental despotism. In the latter framework, Western uniqueness becomes a hybridized development of Oriental despotism rather than the product of unilinear autogeneous development out of the Greek city-state.
     Marx’s theory of history is an ideology—the ideology of Westism. Westism mystifies the uniqueness of the West into a self-developing essence. Westism accounts for the curious lacuna in Marx’s thought, whereby he can recognize interactions between different classes within a society, but not interactions between different societies—even though, according to his own sociology of the East, its characteristic mode of production, unchanged in essence, has stood beside the West throughout the latter’s manifold development. Westism is therefore the proper name for the unidentified ingredient in Marx’s thought, for that “blindness” referred to earlier as the submerged eight-ninths of an intellectual iceberg whose overt expression was anti-Semitism. Marx’s hatred of the Jews and Judaism, no matter how motivated in the personal or biographical sense, reverberated through the rest of his thought in this Westism, an ideology which, because it treats the history of the West as an autogenic process, requires every instance of Eastern influence in and on the West to be viewed as exotic, extraneous, or subversive—which is to say, not truly influential at all, except in the destructive or regressive sense.
     For there is this tremendous paradox: the supposedly self-developing West found it necessary to adopt the ideology of monotheism, an Eastern religion, during its transition from “classical slavery” to feudalism.  This appropriation is extremely peculiar, to say the least, from the standpoint of Marx’s theory of history. If the history of the West truly is the result of self-development, why did it occur under the rubric of an Eastern religious ideology?
     The problem is made all the more poignant by the actual content of the Eastern religion involved. Monotheism is not just a religion of the East, but in a certain sense the quintessential religious expression of Oriental despotism. It contains a religious grasping of the essential principle of Oriental despotism, its theological conceptualization. With the gradual emergence of their religion based on the single, universal God, the Jews were realizing in their heads what geopolitical circumstance kept depriving them of in practice: the imaginary consolidation and perpetuation of their own Oriental despotic empire, comparable in glory and durability to those very real empires in Egypt and Babylon which continually buffeted them. But with this difference: "Yahweh’s" spiritual autocracy, his omniscience, omnipotence and eternality, worshiped not in a private cult of the elite but as the common faith of an entire people, signified the appropriation and internalization by that people of what hitherto had been an exclusive property of the ruling class of Oriental despotism, as well as its governing institutional principle: the principle of a single center of authority, a center to which all action had to be related as so many means to one great end. Denied attainment in an actual despotic state, this principle emerged as monotheistic religious ideology rather than monolithic social organization, which is to say, as the guiding principle of the universe rather than a concrete fact of social life. The means/end calculus became, so to speak, a heuristic salvational device for an entire people just because it was prevented from becoming the elite’s practical administrative device.
     Thus, in Judaic monotheism, where the universal spiritual authority of "Yahweh" replaces the incarnate power of the deified despot, the law replaces the actual bureaucratic structure of his despotic state, and history becomes his field of activity, his empire. This inward ideological leap permitted the Jews to survive the periodic destruction of their state, the discrediting of their temple-cult, the occupation and governing of their land by unclean foreigners, the dislocations of the Diaspora, and the subversive temptations of rival ideologies and ways of life. It allowed these disasters to be reinterpreted as instances of "Yahweh’s" just punishment of his erring people, rather than proofs of "Yahweh’s" weakness against superior alien gods.
     But most important, it made every Jew into a functionary of God. The tremendous psychic dualism which is built into monotheism, based on the gulf between deity and self, provided powerful religious sanction for an ascetic model of conduct, for behavior strictly regulated by rational conformity to God’s written law, rather than by tradition and custom. This ascetic spirit of Judaism differs sharply from the mystical, magical or orgiastic spirit of other popular religions of Oriental despotism. It is based, in Weber’s terminology, on world-rejection rather than world-flight, and stems directly from monotheism’s radical devaluation of the world in favor of the transmundane God in whom alone value subsists. "Yahweh," unlike the gods of mythic religion, cannot be manipulated through appropriate ritual observance and sacrifice as a means of controlling events in this world; he alone is the Great Manipulator, and salvation consists in making oneself, as nearly as possible, his tool, a task requiring vigilant self-policing according to the dictates of his law.
     The ascetic spirit of conduct and rational form of consciousness which this religion engendered had the unintended but vital consequence of predisposing the Jews toward a commercial rather than agricultural way of life—an adaptation without which they never would have survived the impractical geopolitical situation of their state at the crossroads of two great rival empires. The religion never sanctioned rational economic activity per se—this was to be a Protestant and specifically Calvinist innovation—but it encouraged a way of life and habits of thought which made it extremely difficult for a devout Jew to be a farmer, but which lent themselves quite readily to commercial activity. Thus the monotheist ideology not only helped insure the survival of the Jews as a religious-cultural entity, it also indirectly entered into their means of production as a crucial factor in their economic survival as an urban commercial people.
     What monotheism did for the Jews as a people, it did for the West as a civilization. Ascendancy by the Christian sect of Judaism helped Europe to withstand the destruction of the Imperial Roman state without regressing to the tribal barbarism which was indigenous to Europe. It allowed a mode of production to emerge in Europe which was settled and agricultural, without being Asiatic; it preserved in significant part the cultural level of Roman civilization without its stultifying state despotism. It did this not by abandoning the Oriental despotic principle, but by internalizing it, as an ideology rather than a mode of statecraft. This ideology established the spiritual ideal of asceticism, of renunciation of the world and self-renunciation; and this ideal, self-dominion rather than dominion over others, became the unifying cultural principle amid a welter of decentralized local powers. Christian monotheism, in short, made feudalism possible. Feudalism is therefore not the second “stage” in a unilinear sequence of Western development running from antiquity to modern times, but a hybrid synthesis of tribal barbarism’s freedom from centralized state coercion with Oriental despotism’s agrarian mode of production and elevated cultural level.
     It would of course be presumptuous to contend that Christianity’s authority in feudal Europe testifies to the intrinsic power of the monotheistic idea. It is the idea as socially expressed, monotheism in its institutional embodiment, which is historically significant. God’s authority in medieval Europe was wielded by the Vicar of Christ and his priestly bureaucracy, by the Roman Catholic Church. This centralized organization, the material expression of Roman Oriental despotism’s contribution to feudalism, compensated for its lack of total secular power by asserting a claim to total spiritual authority, and it embodied this claim in a bureaucratic type of organization which was qualitatively different from that of feudalism’s other ruling power, the hereditary aristocracy. The very asceticism which made this bureaucratic organization possible, also made it dependent on the aristocracy which controlled the peasantry’s surplus product, for the Church was incapable of self-reproduction while still remaining bureaucratic (a fact enshrined in its rule of priestly celibacy). But the aristocracy in turn was dependent on the Church for the legitimation of its rule to the producing peasantry. And the prestige of the Church, the “charisma” which permitted it to confer this legitimation on secular power, derived from the reverent awe in which the population held it—the awe in which simple worldly people hold any sustained and systematic ascetic rejection of the world.
     It would also be wrong to suppose that monotheism, with or without its institutional embodiment, was bound to play the same role everywhere it gained hegemony that it played in feudal Europe. Byzantine Christianity and Islam are both examples of what could happen to monotheistic religion in social contexts where Oriental despotism is deeply ingrained in the social structure and culture, and in economic contexts incapable of supporting extensive agriculture on the basis of rainfall alone—which require, that is, state-sponsored irrigation and water-control projects in order to become agriculturally productive. In such cases the “power of the ideal” shows itself to be conditional in the extreme, for the monotheist ideology ceases to be a means of transcending Oriental despotism through the ascetic internalization of its dynamic principle, but instead reverts to merely another religious sanctification of Oriental despotism.

     Marx’s reification of the West need not be replaced with another reification—of monotheism itself. It is possible to respect "Yahweh" without believing in him. The unique development of the West depends to a considerable degree on the influence of its monotheist religious ideology, a religion which is Eastern in origin and Eastern in content, and an influence which conveys the West’s Oriental despotic heritage. Monotheism is an important influence but it is not all-important. It is not monotheism, but Marx’s failure to accord it any recognition at all, which is all-important.  It is this failure which turned his theory of Western history into the ideology of Westism. No man whose loathing of the Jews extended even to himself was about to show any respect for their religious creation or their role in history. Quite the contrary; he was bound to construct a world-view which by excluding them exercised his personal demon. His anti-Semitism was thus part and parcel of his inability to acknowledge the West’s debt to the East. His theory of history and his anti-Semitism are intertwined. The theory is not secular, as he thought, but merely pagan; not iconoclastic, but philistine; not scientific, but idolatrous. It is not a theory at all, but an ideology, the ideology of Westism. And this Westism (to which there were many other contributors besides Marx), by celebrating the West as an autogenic miracle and excommunicating the Jews as a pariah people, helped mightily to prepare European acceptance of “a world without Jews,” by insisting on a history in which Jews had no positive part, a sociology which defined them as exotic parasites, and a future in which they would “disappear.” Westism carried the illegitimation of Judaism beyond the bounds of Christian anti-Semitism, into a realm in which final solutions could one day seem both reasonable and humane.




     Marx’s parricidal interpretation of the West’s history took revenge upon him in the East. There he became the very God whose significance for the West he abjured. And the religion founded in his name, Communism, is under severe attack by Westism, just as he personally would have been annihilated had he lived to face the European consequences of Westism. Since the essence of its historical interpretation is the denial of any Western debt to the East, the essence of Westism’s political program is a sanctimonious refusal to make any payments on this non-existent debt—coupled with hypocritical indignation when the consequences of this refusal appear in the form of totalitarianism.
     Communism is a secular religion of the East which uses Oriental despotic methods—the terroristic subjugation of all segments of society by a single coercive center—in order to instill an ascetic ethos in its population and transform its rural, agrarian economy into an urban, industrial one. The religious character of this movement shows up in the ascription by the people of traits to their rulers which are essentially divine—traits of omniscience, benevolence and terrible power. In the prototypal Communist state, the U.S.S.R., during the most frenzied and formative period of its history, these traits coalesced around a single personality. In this period the entire population of the Soviet Union, from the lowliest sweeper of streets to the highest party official, lived in intimate dread of this one man. No foreign or supernatural force imposed his rule on the Soviet people; they imposed it on themselves. The charisma of his terror, like all other forms of charisma, was in the eyes of his beholders; the measure of his authority, only the totality of their obedience.
     The function of this religious movement is the same as the functions of Judaism and Christianity in the West: to mobilize the people against themselves. Communism rules in the name of the people but against their interests. A squalid contradiction, especially viewed from a West which has outgrown its religious roots and can therefore afford to pretend that it never had any—a pretense lying at the heart of Westism. But this contradiction also has its heroic aspect. Out of very little, the Soviets built themselves up into an autonomous power in the world. They did it by transforming themselves from a peasant people into an industrial people. And they used the methods of self-renunciation to do it. That scourge of the people, the Communist Party of the Soviet Union, reserved its greatest violence for itself. The Communist religion does not differ in squalor or heroism from Western religion. Only the intensity and duration of the Soviet religious experience differs from that of the West: what occurred over fifteen centuries of time in Europe, was condensed into a few decades in Russia.
     All the horrors of Stalinism have the same schizoid character: the victims cannot ultimately be distinguished from the perpetrators. Nobody imposed Stalinism on the Soviet people. They built it up from within, from what they had to work with, from their Oriental despotic heritage, from what they were. They reified the coercive side of Oriental despotism, the state autocracy, into a mass totalitarian party, in order to transform tile agrarian-peasant-traditional side into modern industry. It is the same dualism that is built into all asceticism, the same terror-inspired rationality that lies behind the West’s experience of monotheism. There is no rational connection between the arbitrary brutality of Stalinism and the modernization of the Soviet Union. It is because the connection is religious that it was effective, effective in the same way that Calvin’s predestinarian God stimulated Calvinists, as a matter of anxiety-reduction (although not of logic—the logical response would have been fatalistic resignation), to unheard-of feats of rational economic activity.
     Lacking capital with which to finance modernization, primitive accumulation is the only way to modernize. A regime of primitive accumulation means that almost the entire surplus increment of production resulting from more rational economic activity by the people must be withheld from consumption for reinvestment in expanding the means of production. When the people cannot consume the benefits of their intensified economic activity, the greater discipline and self-control—the rational self- consciousness—which is a prerequisite to such activity assumes the form of a regime of externally forced asceticism. Even in communities thoroughly conditioned by ascetic religious values this process took on a theocratic, quasi-totalitarian form (e.g., Puritan New England). But Oriental despotic societies lack such conditioning and must rely almost completely on externally imposed asceticism. Primitive accumulation in such societies can only be enforced by totalitarian methods, rationality can only be sanctioned by terror. Self-control and self-discipline acquire a coercive significance, requiring coercion to be inculcated and coercion to be sustained, when the fruits of the enhanced productivity which such conduct makes possible are expropriated from their producers.
     Even though this expropriation represents in some sense a social appropriation (the surplus is not consumed by a “La Dolce Vita” elite but is reinvested, however inefficiently, in future growth), it is still felt by the individual producers as an exploitative and demoralizing expropriation. The producers may even identify with and take pride in the national economic progress which results from their heroic sacrifices; but since they cannot benefit directly and personally from this progress through higher individual consumption, they require the services of, and may even be said to invent, an external coercive agency, the totalitarian party-state, to stand between them and the product of their labor, the direct consumption of which would undercut modernization. The Stalinist state, which the people execrate but also create, out of their own Oriental despotic heritage, is their alienated symbol of self-restraint. In its inscrutable sovereign arbitrariness, the state is the irrational foundation of their rationality.
     Of course, there is a “variable” in the totalitarian equation. It is not Oriental despotism, which was a fact of Russian history as it is of most of the Third World today. Nor is it the compulsion to modernize, which presented itself to Russia as it presents itself now to all peoples—as a life or death challenge, beyond their free choice. The variable is the primitive accumulation factor. Primitive accumulation is not a historical “given” because the capital necessary to finance the modernization of Russia did exist—in the West, however, not in Russia. It was available, only it was not made available. It remained locked within the property relations of a system which only extrudes it in expectation of a profit. The only profit which would have accrued from an investment in Communist modernization would have been the preclusion of totalitarianism. Much cheaper, really, to propound the ideology of Westism, which tells the East, “We modernized ourselves with capitalist economics and liberal politics. Nobody aided us, but we’ll aid you. Take our political economic doctrines gratis and make something of yourselves.” When the result is Stalinism, its countenance waxes wroth while its eyes well up with crocodile tears for the victims. “See how right we were not to give them one red cent?” The message changes to sanctimonious anti-Communism, which is now telling the West what Westism wants it to hear: that force alone is prophylactic, and that the West’s only complicity in the rise of Stalinism lies in its cowardly unwillingness to apply sufficient force against it.
     The Russian people created Stalinism, but they did not create it according to circumstances of their own choosing. They fashioned it out of their own Oriental despotic heritage, according to the circumstances of primitive accumulation. Russians are responsible for the creation, but Westism is responsible for the circumstances, for it is Westism which guards the illusions of the West about itself. The God whom Westism denies haunts not only the Russian people, but the whole world; his rule is the price the whole world pays for the maintenance of Westist conceit. When we can respect this God, neither denying him nor believing in him, we shall rule ourselves.